
Introduction to Linguistic Philosophy
- Chapters
- Front Matter
- Back Matter
- Subject Index
-
Part I: Foundational Issues
- Chapter 1: Meaning and the Nature of Language
- 1.1. What is Meaning?
- 1.2. Does the Structure of Language Reflect the Structure of the World?
- 1.3. Summary
- Chapter 2: The Semantic Conception of Truth
- 2.1. No Absolute Truth
- 2.2. The Semantic Conception of Truth
- 2.3. Summary
- Chapter 3: Logical Truth and Analyticity
- 3.1. Unconditional and Contingent Truths
- 3.2. Logical Truth
- 3.3. Analyticity
- 3.4. Summary
- Part I: Further Reading
Part II: Naming
- Chapter 4: Names, Sense, and Nominatum
- 4.1. The Name Relation
- 4.2. The Paradox of the Name Relation
- 4.3. Solution to the Paradox of the Name Relation
- 4.4. Summary
- Chapter 5: The Causal Theory of Names
- 5.1. Ordinary Proper Names
- 5.2. Modal Sentences
- 5.3. Epistemic Sentences
- 5.4. Names of Natural Kinds
- 5.5. Summary
- Part II: Further Reading
Part III: Definite Descriptions
- Chapter 6: Description and Analysis
- 6.1. Russell's Theory of Descriptions
- 6.2. The Acquisition of the Referential Function
- 6.3. Three Additional Puzzles Solved by Russell
- 6.4. Scope
- 6.5. Wittgenstein
- 6.6. Summary
- Chapter 7: Descriptions as Names
- 7.1. The Fregean Theory
- 7.2. Referential Descriptions
- 7.3. Summary
- Part III: Further Reading
Part IV: Nonextensional Contexts
- Chapter 8: Modality
- 8.1. What is Logical Modality?
- 8.2. Interchangeability and Existential Generalization
- 8.3. Necessity as a Semantic Predicate
- 8.4. Kripke: Essentialism
- 8.5. Frege-Kaplan: The Middle Way
- 8.6. The Method of Extension and Intension
- 8.7. Summary
- Chapter 9: Propositional Attitudes
- 9.1. What Are Propositional Attitudes?
- 9.2. Interchangeability and Quantifying In
- 9.3. Quine
- 9.4. Kaplan: Cognitive Fixes
- 9.5. Individuating Attitude Objects
- 9.6. Summary
- Part IV: Further Reading
Part V: Generality
- Chapter 10: Indefinite Noun Phrases, Fregean Quantifiers, and Class Theory
- 10.1. Indefinite Noun Phrases
- 10.2. Scope Ambiguities Concerning Indefinite Noun Phrases
- 10.3. Logical Analysis of Indefinite Noun Phrases
- 10.4. Numerically Definite Quantifiers
- 10.5. Expanding the Theory
- 10.6. Summary
- Part V: Further Reading
-
Dedication
This book is dedicated to Palma.
Copyright
Copyright © 1997 by Sage Publications, Inc.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher.
For information:
SAGE Publications, Inc.
2455 Teller Road
Thousand Oaks, California 91320
E-mail: order@sagepub.com
SAGE Publications Ltd.
6 Bonhill Street
London EC2A 4PU
United Kingdom
SAGE Publications India Pvt. Ltd.
M-32 Market
Greater Kailash I
New Delhi 110 048 India
Printed in the United States of America
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Mackenzie, I. E.
Introduction to linguistic philosophy / author, I. E. Mackenzie.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-7619-0174-4. — ISBN 0-7619-0175-2 (pbk.)
1. Language and languages—Philosophy. I. Title.
P106.M27
1997
410′.1—dc21
97-4608
97 98 99 00 01 02 03 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Acquiring Editor: Catherine Rossbach
Editorial Assistant: Kathleen Derby
Production Editor: Diana E. Axelsen
Production Assistant: Denise Santoyo
Typesetter/Designer: Christina M. Hill
Indexer: Virgil Diodato
Cover Designer: Ravi Balasuriya
Print Buyer: Anna Chin
Introduction
The Scope of this BookLinguistics is the empirical study of natural languages. Philosophy of language is concerned with the underlying nature of the phenomena that linguists study. And linguistic philosophy is an approach to the philosophy of language. This approach is perhaps exemplified best by Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, which stresses the importance of always seeing how language is used rather than assuming it to conform to some preexisting logical structure.
This book is about philosophy of language in general, but the conception of meaning that emerges is fundamentally Wittgensteinian in inspiration. It is designed above all for linguists with an interest in the deeper issues of their science, although it may well be of interest to anyone of a philosophical disposition. It presupposes no prior acquaintance either with the philosophy of language or with linguistic theory.
The book's aim is to give the reader a solid foundation in the field. As a consequence, it is concerned primarily with the grandees of linguistic analysis: Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, Carnap, Quine, and so on. Anyone who has read and understood the book should feel equipped to deal with advanced work on most topics in semantics and philosophy of language.
Some Important TermsAlthough this book does not presuppose any technical knowledge, there are a number of terminological distinctions that are made so frequently that some acquaintance with them is essential.
Sentence and UtteranceA sentence is an abstract unit constructed according to appropriate syntactic rules. For example, of the following two expressions,
(1) Smith is raking the leaves,
(2) Raking the leaves,
only (1) counts as a sentence in English.
Sentences are realized in discourse through utterances. For example, all performances of Hamlet begin with the same sentence but a different utterance.
The term ‘utterance’ is actually ambiguous, because it denotes both the act of uttering something, as in
(3) His utterance of those words provoked much amusement,
and the product of this act, as in
(4) That was a rather objectionable utterance.
Some linguists disambiguate between the two senses, employing the expressions ‘utterance act’ and ‘utterance signal’, respectively. In this book, the single term ‘utterance’ is used because the context is generally sufficient for disambiguation.
Sentence and PropositionA proposition is taken to be what is expressed by a declarative sentence (used with assertoric force). From that perspective, the proposition expressed by a sentence p in English is identical to the proposition expressed by any sentence, in any language, that is synonymous with p.
Propositions are often identified with the objects of belief, assertion, and so on in sentences such as these:
(5) Amanda believes that England will never win the football world cup.
(6) John said that a gale was blowing.
The subordinate clause in these and similar sentences is often held to designate a proposition.
Use and MentionA linguistic expression may be used to make a statement, ask a question, issue a command, and so on, but it may also be mentioned. Consider the name ‘London’ in the following sentences:
(7) London is the capital of Great Britain.
(8) ‘London’ contains six letters.
In (7), the word ‘London’ is a name of the city London. That is to say, the sentence is about London. In this case, the name ‘London’ has simply been used, in accordance with the general conventions governing its application. Sentence (8), on the other hand, is about the name ‘London’: It does not assert that the city London contains eight letters. Thus, in sentence (8), the expression ‘London’ is not used but mentioned, which is why it appears between inverted commas or single quotation marks.
The distinction between use and mention can be generalized into a distinction between object languages and metalanguages. An object language is a language viewed as an object of study or semantic analysis. The metalanguage is the language in which statements about the object language are made. Thus (8) is a metalinguistic sentence.
Extensional and NonextensionalNormally, any two expressions standing for the same object can be exchanged one for the other without altering the truth-value of the containing sentence. For example, the two descriptions ‘the capital of Peru’ and ‘the south American city with the oldest university’ both designate the same thing, namely, Lima; so just as the sentence
(9) The capital of Peru is on the River Rímac is true, so is
(10) The south American city with the oldest university is on the River Rímac.
The principle just illustrated follows naturally enough from the idea that if one thing is identical to another, anything that is true of the one must be true of the other; this principle holds good for a very large number of cases. The contexts in which it holds are called extensional contexts. Contexts where it does not hold are called, unsurprisingly, nonextensional contexts. Sentence (11) below exhibits a nonextensional context,
(11) Jones thinks that Isaac Newton died in 1727, for the truth of (11) does not secure the truth of
(12) Jones thinks that the author of Opticks died in 1727,
despite the fact that Newton and the author of Opticks are one and the same.
The Structure of the BookThe philosophical study of language is not a systematic program. Rather, particular aspects of language have received substantial treatment because they are considered to be of fundamental conceptual significance. The structure of this book reflects this circumstance and contains discussions only of those areas of language that are of genuine philosophical interest.
The book is divided into five sections. The first is concerned with foundational issues, such as truth, meaning, and the nature of language. The other four deal with the specific linguistic phenomena that have attracted the most philosophical attention, that is, names, descriptions, nonextensional contexts, and quantification. There is no “core” to the book, in the sense of one or more chapters being more important than the others. Nor is it absolutely necessary to start at the beginning. Thus Chapter 10 may be attempted before Chapter 6 and so on. Where a chapter presupposes an understanding of something that is explained elsewhere in the book, a specific cross-reference is always given.
Acknowledgments
I wish to acknowledge the help of the following people: Jenny Saul, Nigel Armstrong, Andrew Linn, Alex Schwartz, Jim Hurford, and my parents. Any remaining errors are entirely my responsibility.
-
References
1985. Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity. Volume 2: An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell., and1984. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy4: 159–219. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00350139, and1964. A Companion to Wittgenstein's ‘Tractatus’. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.1993. Formal Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO97811391663171956. Meaning and Necessity.2nd edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.1958. Introduction to Semantics and Formalization of Logic (2 volumes in one). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.1990. Meaning and Grammar: An Introduction to Semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press., and1986. Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. Convergence, N.Y.: Praeger.1990. Language and problems of knowledge. Lecture delivered in Madrid, April 28, 1986. Printed in The Philosophy of Language, edited by A.R.Martinich (pp. 509–527).2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.1936. A note on the Entscheidungsproblem. Journal of Symbolic Logic1: 40–41, 101–102. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/22693261950. On Carnap's analysis of statements of assertion and belief. Analysis10: 97–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/analys/10.5.97Cole, P., and Morgan, J.L., eds. 1975. Syntax and Semantics. Volume 3. New York: Academic Press.1985. Structured Meanings. Cambridge: MIT Press.1992. Context in the attitudes. Linguistics and Philosophy15: 185–198. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF006358061967. Truth and Meaning. Synthèse17: 304–323.1966. Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review75: 281–304. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/21831431973. The causal theory of names. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 47: 187–208.Feigl, H., and Sellars, W, eds. 1949. Readings in Philosophical Analysis. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.1949. On sense and nominatum. In Readings in Philosophical Analysis, edited by H.Feigl and WSellars (pp. 85–102). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.1953. The Foundations of Arithmetic: A Logico-Mathematical Inquiry into the Concept of Number. Translated by J.L.Austin.2nd edition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.1960. Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege. Edited by P.Geach and M.Black.2nd edition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.1964. The Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Translated by . Berkeley: University of California Press.1971. Ecrits logiques et philosophiques. Translated by . Paris: Points.1972. Conceptual Notation and Related Articles. Translated by . Oxford: Clarendon.French, P.A., Uehling, T.E., and Wettstein, H.K., eds. 1979. ContemporaryPerspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.French, P.A., Uehling, T.E., and Wettstein, H.K., eds. 1981. Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.1975. Logic and conversation. In Syntax and Semantics, edited by P.Cole and J.L.Morgan (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic Press., and1977. A Companion to Wittgenstein's ‘Philosophical Investigations’. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.1968–1969. Quantifying in. Synthèse19: 178–214.1972. What is Russell's Theory of Descriptions? In Bertrand Russell, edited by D.F.Pears (pp. 227–244). Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Books.1973. Wittgenstein. London: Penguin.1995. Frege. London: Penguin.1979a. A puzzle about belief. In Meaning and Use. Papers Presented at the Second Jerusalem Philosophical Encounter, April 1976, edited by A.Margalit (pp. 239–283). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.1979b. Speaker's reference and semantic reference. In Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, edited by P.A.French, T.E.Uehling and H.K.Wettstein (pp. 6–27).1980. Naming and Necessity.2nd edition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. An Elementary Exposition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.1977. Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.1995. Lingusitic Semantics: An Introduction. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO97805118102131981. A proposed solution to a puzzle about belief. In Midwest Studies in Philosophy, edited by P.A.French, T.E.Uehling and H.K.Wettstein (pp. 501–510). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press..Margalit, Avishai, Ed. 1979. Meaning and Use. Papers Presented at the Second Jerusalem Philosophical Encounter, April 1976. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Martinich, A.E., Ed. 1990. The Philosophy of Language.2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.1967. A System of Logic..8th edition. London: Longman.Pears, D.F., Ed. 1972. Bertrand Russell. Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor.1979. Comments on Kripke's ‘Puzzle About Belief’. In Meaning and Use. Papers Presented at the Second Jerusalem Philosophical Encounter, April 1976, edited by A.Margalit (pp. 284–288). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.1943. Notes on existence and necessity. Journal of Philosophy40: 113–127. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/20174581949. Designation and existence. In Readings in Philosophical Analysis, edited by H.Feigl and WSellars (pp. 44–51). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.O.1950. Methods of Logic. New York: Holt.O. O.1953. Three grades of modal involvement. Proceedings of the XIth International Congress of Philosophy, Volume 14 (pp. 65–81), Brussels, August.O.1956. Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy53: 177–187. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2022451O.1960. Word and Object. Cambridge: MIT Press.O.1990. Prepositional Attitudes: An Essay on Thoughts and How We Ascribe Them. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO97805116252821919a. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin.1919b. Propositions: What they are and how they mean. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplement II, 1–43.1921. Analysis of Mind. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.1937. Denoting. In Principles of Mathematics (pp. 53–65).2nd edition. New York: Norton.1959. The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford Paperbacks University Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (First published 1912)1994. Las oraciones compuestas en Aymara. In Language in the Andes, edited by P.Cole, G.Hermon, and M.D.Martin (pp. 126–150). Newark, Del.: Latin American Studies., and1938. Gesammelte Aufsätze 1926–36. Vienna: Gerold.1983. Intentionality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.1949. The semantic conception of truth. In Readings in Philosophical Analysis, edited by H.Feigl and WSellars (pp. 52–84). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.1983. Logic, Semantics and Metamathematics. Translated by J.H.Woodger.2nd edition. Oxford: Clarendon.1965. The Principles of Linguistic Philosophy. Edited by R.Harré. London: Macmillan.1953. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by . Oxford: Basil Blackwell.1961. Notebooks 1914–1916. Edited by G.H.von Wright and G.E. M.Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.1961 (first published 1921). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by and . London: Routledge.About the Author
I. E. Mackenzie is currently Lecturer (Assistant Professor) in the School of Modern Languages at the University of Newcastle upon Tyne. He was educated at the universities of Oxford and Cambridge. His doctoral dissertation was on the semantics of Spanish verbal categories and was supervised by John Lyons. His research interests are diverse, ranging from the philosophy of language to Spanish and Latin American linguistics. He has published articles and reports on the philosophy of language, Spanish semantics, and language contact in the Andes.
-
166013- Loading...
Also from SAGE Publishing
- CQ Library American political resources opens in new tab
- Data Planet A universe of data opens in new tab
- Lean Library Increase the visibility of your library opens in new tab
- SAGE Journals World-class research journals opens in new tab
- SAGE Research Methods The ultimate methods library opens in new tab
- SAGE Stats Data on demand opens in new tab